Cookies help us deliver our services. By using our services, you agree to our use of cookies. Learn more.
  • Log In
  • Register
CEEOL Logo
Advanced Search
  • Home
  • SUBJECT AREAS
  • PUBLISHERS
  • JOURNALS
  • eBooks
  • GREY LITERATURE
  • CEEOL-DIGITS
  • INDIVIDUAL ACCOUNT
  • Help
  • Contact
  • for LIBRARIANS
  • for PUBLISHERS

Content Type

Subjects

Languages

Legend

  • Journal
  • Article
  • Book
  • Chapter
  • Open Access
  • Philosophy
  • Philosophical Traditions
  • Analytic Philosophy

We kindly inform you that, as long as the subject affiliation of our 300.000+ articles is in progress, you might get unsufficient or no results on your third level or second level search. In this case, please broaden your search criteria.

Result 761-780 of 923
  • Prev
  • 1
  • 2
  • 3
  • ...
  • 38
  • 39
  • 40
  • ...
  • 45
  • 46
  • 47
  • Next
Przesycenie. Koncepcje Jürgena Habermasa i Jeana Baudrillarda na tle katastrofizmu neohumanistycznego St. I. Witkiewicza

Przesycenie. Koncepcje Jürgena Habermasa i Jeana Baudrillarda na tle katastrofizmu neohumanistycznego St. I. Witkiewicza

Author(s): Agnieszka Smrokowska-Reichmann / Language(s): Polish Issue: 30/2015

The paper analyses the category of neo-catastrophism. Postmodern society has launched the mechanisms of self-destruction which are now working not only in interpersonal and communicative relationships, but also in the realms of axiology, ethics and even ontology. According to the author, the main aspects of Jean Baudrillard’s and Jürgen Habermas’ philosophy can be interpreted as containing such neo-catastrophic message. However, as the forerunner of neo-catastrophism in philosophy the author points out Stanisław Ignacy Witkiewicz (Witkacy), especially his theory of metaphysical feelings and their disappearance in mass society. Stanisław Ignacy Witkiewicz, known among the philosophy critics as neohumanistic catastrophist, has foreseen many categories which are typical for Habermas’ and Baudrillard’s writings. The neo-catastrophic mechanisms has a serious consequences for the condition of postmodern subject, the more so because the main part of the neocatastrophism is the strong conviction that there is no escape. The author, besides the main thesis mentioned above, highlights some common features between Baudillard’s and Habermas’ conceptions.

More...
Czy model Wszechświata powinien być strukturalnie stabilny?

Czy model Wszechświata powinien być strukturalnie stabilny?

Author(s): Paweł Tambor,Marek Szydłowski / Language(s): Polish Issue: 1/2017

We show that the modern cosmology appears to be the case of effective modeling similar to the Standard Model of particle physics (SM). In the study of the universe an important role is played by the physical theory from which the Standard Cosmological Model, allowing us to explain the properties of contemporary universe and its history, is derived. The Standard Cosmological Model includes the model of universe evolution (based on General Relativity) and SM. This paper discusses the scheme of the accelerated expansion of the universe in terms of today's dark energy and dark matter. We will examine the methodological features of such an explanation in the Standard Cosmological Model. We elaborate oscillating models of the Universe from the point of view of their structural stability. We show that this conceptual framework can be useful in describing relations between cosmological models LCDM (Lamda – Cold – Dark Matter Model) and CMD where epistemological emergence of specific properties is presented in terms of bifurcation and instability.

More...
Scholastique Mukasonga: Témoignage littéraire et recherche d’identité culturelle dans l’entre-deux

Scholastique Mukasonga: Témoignage littéraire et recherche d’identité culturelle dans l’entre-deux

Author(s): Julia Pfeiffer / Language(s): French Issue: 1/2014

Après avoir donné un bref aperçu de l’auteure Scholastique Mukasonga et son oeuvre, l’article suivant cherche à réaliser une analyse concernant la situation de publication de celle-ci et le statut en tant qu’écrivaine exilée en France. Il s’agit d’un positionnement dans le champ littéraire européen et cela peut être confirmé entre autre par le biais de la réponse aux questions importantes du lecteur qu’elle cible de son oeuvre ainsi que la fonction de son témoignage, notamment la transmission de sa mémoire et la recherche de son identité culturelle dans cette situation postcoloniale.

More...

Praktički silogizam kod Aristotela i Hegela

Author(s): Milenko A. Perović / Language(s): Serbian Issue: 2/2004

Nach einer Darstellung der gegenwärtigen Diskussion über die Gedanklichkeit des menschlichen Handelns im Rahmen der analytischen Philosophie, die zur Abhandlung über den praktischen Schluss wurde, kehrt der Autor zur Interpretation der traditionellen Lehren über den praktischen Schluss zurück. Im Mittelpunkt seiner Interpretation ist die Rekonstruktion von Aristoteles’ Lehre vom praktischen Schluss und Hegels Lehre von der „Schluss des Handelns“. Der Autor vertritt die These, dass Hegel, Aristoteles’ Lehre über den praktischen Schluss folgend, das teleologische Prinzip in der Philosophie neu begründet und epochal weiterentwickelt hat.

More...

The Conception of Bernard Bolzano About the Continuum and the Achievements of Contemporary Mathematics

Author(s): Vesselin Petrov / Language(s): English Issue: 2/2004

The present paper is devoted to the contribution of the eminent philosopher and mathematician Bernard Bolzano to the problem of continuum. The paper consists of two parts. In the first part it is compared the conception of Bolzano about the continuum with that of Aristotle. Bolzano’s view includes two essential moments: first, that the continuum is composed of noncontinual elements (points), and second, that two points which are at a certain distance one to other cannot compose a continuum. Aristotle has two definitions about continuity: in the first one he in fact develops the idea of continuity as a physical connectedness, and in the second one he emphasizes the infinite divisibility of the continuum. The second part of the paper gives an evaluation of Bolzano’s contribution to the problem of continuum in comparison with the achievements of the contemporary mathematics on the problem. There is a tendency to consider continuity in two senses: as an infinite divisibility and as a connectedness. The contemporary topology (as a branch of mathematics) develops the concept of continuity in the second sense. Bolzano’s conception bears in some respects the resemblance to the contemporary definitions in topology of the concepts of closeness, neighborhood, isolated point, etc. His definition about the continuum can be considered as a remote precursor of the contemporary topological definition of continuity as connectedness.

More...

Norms as Decisions

Author(s): Vihren Bouzov / Language(s): English Issue: 2/2004

The fundamental ontological categories of Aristotle are in language (Cateories, IV 25). They are ontological. Norms are not in this classification. They are not descriptive propositions - they can not be true or false. But the logical tradition is concerned with norms as linguistic entities. It is justified by the ideas of Aristotle. The linguistic approach leads to some theoretical difficulties of the contemporary logic of norms. [...]

More...

Upotreba metafizike ukoliko je ona povezana sa geometrijom, u filozofiji prirode čija prva proba sadrži fizičku monadologiju

Author(s): Immanuel Kant / Language(s): Serbian Issue: 1/2004

Filozofi oštrijeg suda koj i se trude oko ispitivanja prirodnih stvari slažu se u uverenju da moramo sa najvećom brižljivošću da sprečimo da se u prirodnu nauku uvuče ono što je izmišljeno nekim srećn i m obrtom ili na temelju neke nepromišljenosti, kao i da se preduzima bilo šta neizvesno bez saglasnosti iskustva i bez posredovnja geometrije. Sigurno da ne bi moglo da se pretpostavi bilo šta što bi bi lo blagotvornije i korisnije za filozofiju od ove od luke. Pošto, verovatno, jedva da je nekome od smrtnika dopušteno da čvrstim koracima napreduJe na pravom putu istine, a da pri rom tu i tamo ne odstupi u stranu, onda su neki ovaj zakon do te mere razvili da se uopšte više ne usuđuju da se u ispitivanju istine otisnu na puč inu , već smatraju da je zgodn ije da jedre duž obale: oni su dozvoli li pristup samo onome što je neposredno poznato putem svedočanstva iskustva. A zapravo, na ovom putu možemo pouzdano da raščlanimo zakone prirode, ali ne i poreklo i uzroke zakona. Jer, onaj ko samo sledi prirodne pojave, uvek ostaje jednako udaljen od razumevanja prvih uzroka koj i leže daleko, i ism tako malo će da dospe do nauke o prirodi samih tela kao i onaj ko se sve više penje na vrh nekog brda zanoseć i se da će konačno dodirnuti rukom nebo. [...]

More...

Raționalitatea științifică și alte tipuri de raționalitate

Author(s): Alexandru Boboc / Language(s): Romanian Issue: 1/2019

The text presented here illustrates the work and deep worldview that Academician Alexandru Boboc promoted his entire life: rationalism; and this means all the way. Why rationalism and what does it mean? It is, first, the substantiation of humans’ positions about what is constant and generally efficient in their relationships with and in the world. The basis of what is constant and generally efficient is not the idea/the world of ideas as such, but the “true judgement with an account”, as Plato said long before (Theaetetus, 201c): the logically correct judgement based on semantically correct information. The reasoned judgement is always about concrete things, but since these things are transient, how can the human rationality – that takes its power from its ability to unite in abstract schemes what it has discriminated before – be lasting? It can, just because it does not end with its abstract designs, but ascends to the comprehension of the many facets of the concrete. Thus, the correct information as such is never the simple one-sided content eventually implied in the premises: on the contrary, it supposes the reciprocal confrontation of the different aspects of the concrete and their analysis. Alexandru Boboc’s passion, in the frame of his larger specialisation in history of philosophy, is the modern thinking. From the always contradictory phenomena arisen in the modern intellectual vortex, he alwaysinsisted on what the modern philosophy has demonstrated in such a way that, on the basis of judgements, the return to irrational stances to no longer be possible. In this respect, he has as poles Kant and Hegel. Human knowledge starts from the human experience and no one can avoid this empirical origin, but human knowledge is more than a collection of data about transient things: it is, certainly, even more than the first abstract schemes of the intellect; it is the living picture of the never ended complex of connections and viewpoints. The order put by human thinking in the world as it is conceived is not opposed to its openness: it suggests pluralism but, at the same time, this is not drowned in relativism. The human rationality – judging and measuring the causes, the necessary and the contingency, and the consequences – is the only one that prevents the incidents from turning maleficent for human life. The human rationality is thus the only one that foresees its results from the nunc – since the judgements are already models of/for the future, the humans do not judge only after the outcomes turned out – and also that anticipates, starting from the models of the future in order to avoid present bad individual, isolated and short-termed reckonings. The text points just the epistemological logic of the modern rationalism. This logic was called “criticism” by Kant, while Hegel has used and developed both the meanings of criticism and of dialectic, beyond the ancient origins of this last word and method. From an epistemological point of view, the greatness of Kant and Hegel stands in the reciprocal rationale of rationalism and criticism: rationalism means the decomposition of ideas and their multiple judgements, not the alignment to the argument from authority, and thus it puts the premises of every idea under question; criticism is just the rejection of the appeal to authority and thus it arrives to question the premises themselves, and this entire process becomes an inherent movement of the human spirit in front of the world. This methodological contribution of the modern rationalism is cardinal. The dialectical understanding of nature involves both formal models – mathematical, as they were exploded in modernity – subordinated to focused demonstrations and reproductions of sequential causality, and also holistic interpretations, search for correlations and meanings from a more and more multilateral standpoint. Thus, the dialectical understanding is the reason for integrating science and philosophy. The Kant and Hegel’s use of metaphysics and their insistence on it were not their simple reflex of old denominations but, on the contrary, the suggestion that by focusing on the “last causes”, philosophy questions the premises of every reasonable and non-reasonable argumentation. But if so, the modern rationalism is the ground of a critical humanism. Alexandru Boboc has inferred from the modern rationalist principles just the search for the meaning of the human life. And if the quiddity of rationalism is its (concrete) universalism, it emphasises the importance of every individual, rejecting the selfishness. The meaning of life is for every human being, the universalism of rationalism does not send to selective treatment of humans in the name of apparently clever abstract ideas. By searching the meanings of the world, of the ideas and of human life, the human rationality proves to be “spirit”, namely, the self-conscious and self-determining, rational capacity to be both negation – critique, from banter to cold dissolution – and positive construction full of fantasy but conducted by values. Therefore, though 14Alexandru BobocNOEMA XVIII, 2019 the autonomy of the object – namely, of all kinds of objects, including the means to create objects and the reactive and creative attitudes and processes – from the human subject might induce the idea that there would be regions of existence marked only by the specificity of tackling them, in fact the “types” of rationality never exclude the common features of the reason and, thus, of the good and the beautiful. They are types of experience, but the beacon is rationalism. This avoids reductionism, related to either the enthusiastic optimism concerning science (and technology) or to a pessimistic stance towards them. And rationalism never simplifies the world and the human representations, but allows very different and even falsifiable theories: these theories and their premises are valuable even when they are falsified, but only if the method outlining them is scientific (rationalist) and suggests the value of scientific honesty. For this reason, the model is for Alexandru Boboc that of the nascent modernity, never excluding from rationality the human values: because the reason and its creation – the world 3, in Popper’s formula – are never autonomous from the human society. Truth, together with reason, method and value, are paradigm-concepts of philosophy, reminded us Alexandru Boboc. The theoretical model of Alexandru Boboc, taken over from Kant and Hegel, is opposed to the “spiritualist” pseudo-philosophy erected on premises never put under question, and as if philosophy and science would not have any other answer since the world flows outside them. No: both the Kant and Hegel’s rationalism and the theoretical model of Alexandru Boboc involve the responsibility of philosophy, since first and foremost philosophy is the conscience of science/reasonable knowledge, substantiating its process of awareness. This function and peculiarity of philosophy – i.e. of rationalism – was the reason why Alexandru Bobochas done and is doing his enquiries in the history of philosophy. This means the description of the history of arguments related to the understanding of the world. He quotes very often from the past philosophers, emphasising the core of their thinking: from a didactic standpoint, so that the readers do not retain words about them, but just that core; from a methodological standpoint, so that the readers do not repeat the historical form of the past thinkers, but go forward. Philosophy and science means to going forward. This is their responsibility. We are not allowed to abstain from rationalism and to do as if we would say something new. Indeed, we must say something new with the help of rationalism! Only in this manner may the present European spirit develop. And certainly: not only European. This spirit is, obviously, different from its traditions but, Alexandru Boboc accentuates, we have to treat them with the means of rationalism, and thus never forget their modern source, since only in this way we can understand that, in front of so many confusions tending to annul these means, what is important and unique is the human – rational – quest for the meanings of human life. Rationalism all the way doesn’t mean “scientism”, a viewpoint never shared by scientists and only caricatured by those thinkers who were either opposed to science or did not understand it and the relations between science and philosophy. Alexandru Boboc has long before insisted on the difference between thescientific spirit and “scientism”, advancing at the same time the rationalist principles consisting of and leading to coherence, criteria and disclosing of contradictions. Only in this way, not fearing contradictions, both the universalistic view about our appurtenance to the same and unique species and the value we give to the unique and unrepeatable individual existence are possible.Noema celebrates Academician Alexandru Boboc before the 20th of February 2020 when he will be 90 years old. He is an example of generosity: he works and publishes even nowadays, in order to better disclose the history of philosophical ideas; he translates from the modern German and Italian thinkers even nowadays; he emits professional and educational messages during conferences and his relations with researchers. Hispersonality lights here the necessity of rationalism, of self-reflexivity in science and all human activities, and the necessity of self-scrutiny for all the researchers and human beings.

More...
The Mind of the Political and Social Animal

The Mind of the Political and Social Animal

Author(s): Nerijus Stasiulis / Language(s): English Issue: 3/2019

In this article I present the outline of Filosofija. Sociogija 30(3) the articles of which I see as mainly centering around the issue of Man as placed and interacting within social, cultural and political contexts. However, the discussion of the social or political is generally nourished by metaphysical or epistemological issues or insights. The human mind deals with the fundamental questions concerning human nature, the existence or the metaphysical structure of the world, the status of cognition in general and science/ technology in particular. The articles merge into a choir signalling the inescapably social and political mode of our consciousness.

More...
Intelekto antrojo veiksmo aiškinimas scholastinėje logikoje Lietuvoje XVI a. antrojoje pusėje

Intelekto antrojo veiksmo aiškinimas scholastinėje logikoje Lietuvoje XVI a. antrojoje pusėje

Author(s): Vytis Valatka / Language(s): Lithuanian Issue: 38/2004

The analysis of the second operation of the human intellect presented in lectures on logics by the main representatives of scholastic logic in Lithuania of the second half of the sixteenth century, Marcin Úmiglecki and Diego Ortiz, virtually belongs to the so-called major logic (logica major). That is, the cardinal object of the above-mentioned analysis was the content of proposition. On the other hand, such an analysis involved some elements of dialectics, or minor logic (logica minor sive dialectica), namely, certain rules of logical square and conversion. Following the Aristotelian-scholastic tradition, Úmiglecki and Ortiz defined the proposition as a correct or false sentence (oratio vera sive falsa). Meanwhile, opposition, equivalence (aequipollentia) and convertibility were regarded as the main properties of proposition (propria propositionis). These properties were also interpreted in the spirit of the scholastic tradition. Úmiglecki and Ortiz traditionally considered necessary propositions the main elements of scientific knowledge. As for the terms of necessary proposition, it was affirmed that neither subject nor predicate ought to bear actual existence. That is, two conditions alone are necessary for these terms: a) there must be at least a logical potentiality (potentia logica) for the existence of a subject (that is, the subject needs not be a contradictory being, such as a circular square); b) such an existence having been assumed, the predicate must be inseparable from the existing subject.

More...
Marxo ir Engelso visuomeninės pažinimo teorijos link ir aplink

Marxo ir Engelso visuomeninės pažinimo teorijos link ir aplink

Author(s): Aivaras Stepukonis / Language(s): Lithuanian Issue: 38/2004

The social theory of knowledge developed by Marx and Engels is unfolded in three steps: (1) by explaining the meaning of dialectic as a form both of thinking and of being; (2) by discussing the anthropological and historical materialism that pervades the original Marxist epistemological perspective; (3) by presenting Marx’s and Engels’ belief that the material means and relations of production determine the existence of society in all respects; (4) by isolating the multiple senses of ideology as they occur in the writings of Marx and Engels and by discussing the various methods of unmasking the hidden agendas of ideologies. Throughout the article, a clear and sympathetic exposition of Marxist social epistemology is combined with an insightful and playful criticism of several inconsistencies that the author of the article finds in Marx’s and Engels’ accounts of things.

More...
Marxo ir Engelso visuomeninės pažinimo teorijos link ir aplink

Marxo ir Engelso visuomeninės pažinimo teorijos link ir aplink

Author(s): Aivaras Stepukonis / Language(s): Lithuanian Issue: 37/2004

The social theory of knowledge developed by Marx and Engels is unfolded in three steps: (1) by explaining the meaning of dialectic as a form both of thinking and of being; (2) by discussing the anthropological and historical materialism that pervades the original Marxist epistemological perspective; (3) by presenting Marx’s and Engels’ belief that the material means and relations of production determine the existence of society in all respects; (4) by isolating the multiple senses of ideology as they occur in the writings of Marx and Engels and by discussing the various methods of unmasking the hidden agendas of ideologies. Throughout the article, a clear and sympathetic exposition of Marxist social epistemology is combined with an insightful and playful criticism of several inconsistencies that the author of the article finds in Marx’s and Engels’ accounts of things.

More...

Парадигмальні аспекти взаємодії психоанализу й арт-терапії: проблема якісної класифікації психотипів (закінчення)

Author(s): Galina Popoyena Poserezhna / Language(s): Ukrainian Issue: 39/2017

Purpose of Article. The article substantiates the psychological type classification based on universal ontological grounds, and demonstrates an ability to scan psychic characteristics of an individual. Thus, the mentioned idea provides an effective interaction of practices based on the psychoanalysis and art therapy. The certain claim opens the space for the actual interaction of psychoanalytic and art-therapy practices. Methodology. The methodology of the study applies methods of classification and typological analysis as well as integral and symbolic-numeric approaches. Their application allows to reveal the disadvantages of the existing quantitative classifications of psychological types and to offer the universal and qualitative ones instead. Scientific Novelty. The scientific novelty of the article is presented through the fundamentally new method of psychological types classification practice. The approach appeals to the conglomeration of objective psychic modes that form a certain psychological type (altogether there are 16 of them, which are systemically represented). In addition, the logical justification for the selection of mental functions, which are taken into account in the proposed qualitative classification, is provided for the first time. As a result, each person appears as a carrier of an exclusively individual set of specific mental qualities, unique as to their "bouquet," which can be "woven" from objective data, rather than reflections of a psychoanalyst. Conclusions. Only by using a qualitative classification of psychological types, psycho- and art therapy-related practices will develop a strong paradigmatic basis, thus, combining their actual ontological aspects in harmonious coherence, and allowing to accelerate the psychodiagnostic process radically. At the same time, from the scientific and theoretical perspective, the developed method will open new channel of the essence of man as a cosmic phenomenon realization.

More...
Новата монография на Веселин Петров върху Уайтхед
4.50 €
Preview

Новата монография на Веселин Петров върху Уайтхед

Author(s): Serghey Gherdjikov / Language(s): Bulgarian Issue: 1/2020

Vesselin Petrov's new book on Whitehead is an analysis of “some specific features of his teachings, such as his views concerning rationality, dynamic holism, things and objects, events, anticipation, creativity, nature, organism, and life” (Petrov, 2019: 7). The book is a real achievement for the genre: a monographic thematical study of a comprehensive author's philosophy as “a philosophy of organism”. Alfred Whitehead is a unique, difficult to understand thinker who introduces new concepts and new meanings of traditional and modern concepts. Prof. Vesselin Petrov is an author of a series of works on Whitehead and processual philosophy and editor of collections of articles on processual philosophy and Whitehead. The author is one of the leaders in modern Whiteheadianism. Professor Petrov has been the Executive Director (2015 – 2017) of the International Process Network. Whitehead is a unique thinker who creates a philosophy entirely of a non-classical type. Whitehead's philosophy is postmodern in the meaning introduced twenty years before French postmodernism as a constructive outcome of Modernism. For Whitehead, unique, modernism proves to be anti-rational. His philosophy is different from both the continental and the analytic.

More...
Derrida, Chomsky and Wittgenstein: Grammatologist / Grammarian / Grammatist

Derrida, Chomsky and Wittgenstein: Grammatologist / Grammarian / Grammatist

Author(s): Prakash Kona / Language(s): English Issue: 4/2011

That there is no fixed point but point(s) of origin is the point of origin of this essay that begins with a play on the word gram. It could be the Derridean gramme or Chomskyean grammar. It could also be “language-game” meant to bring Wittgenstein into the conversation. I used Alfred Hitchcock’s statement on psychoanalysis taken from the 1945 classic “Spellbound” as a point of “origin” for the discussion on grammar. The statement concentrates on the “origins” of the problems of the mind that psychoanalysis hopes to cure. In using Hitchcock, more of artist of language than a language-theorist, I problematize the idea of origin itself; whether it ought to come from a serious-minded philosopher like Freud - the so-called “right” source or a secondary source such as Hitchcock playing with the Freudean idea of psychoanalysis through his narrative. The origin of discussion thus turns out to be a false start. It serves a purpose in showing the apparent nature of the text that psychoanalysis is a construction like any other discourse that dominated Western philosophy from Plato to the present. Yet origin must exist in the literal sense of the term. Freud did off er psychoanalysis as a form of therapy to open the text to meaning - in this case, the text is the human mind itself. In the process, psychoanalysis itself is a multifaceted text that becomes a stage for the entrance of the gram. The idea is to show philosophy as a narrative; the narrative dimension of philosophy and philosophy itself as a form of narration. From a Derridean perspective, the point of origin is a null, which opens the text to diverse readings. It is both the anarchy of the text as well as silence at the heart of language.

More...
Revitalizacija antičke i srednjovjekovne filozofije u mišljenju Josefa Piepera

Revitalizacija antičke i srednjovjekovne filozofije u mišljenju Josefa Piepera

Author(s): Franjo Mijatović / Language(s): Croatian Issue: 4/2019

In the article, we will try to present the fundamental meaning and significance of philosophizing, more precisely the philosophical act, of the Christian thinker Josef Pieper. He sees the reason for the revitalization of antique and medieval philosophy in the possibility of a far-wider understanding of the entirety of the world which concerns the entirety of being in all its (non)occurrence. While contemporary philosophy held debates on the truth between hermeneutic and analytical philosophy, Pieper remains loyal to his antique and medieval teachers, especially Plato and Aquinas. Although Pieper’s thought is deeply imbued with thoughts of the said two, it is in no way, which is the aim this article, limited to the mere repetition or compilation of what was said long ago. In this regard, Pieper argues that a tradition, such as the Platonic and the Thomist, can be an example to all other traditions, and serve as the real model of human rational philosophical research, and philosophizing as a possibility of divine-human event in search of the truth.

More...
Математические аспекты архитектурной логики формообразования римского Пантеона

Математические аспекты архитектурной логики формообразования римского Пантеона

Author(s): Andrey Radzyukevich,Gennadi Grigorenko / Language(s): Russian Issue: 1/2020

The paper tests the methodology of architectural and ethnographic research of the object of material culture-a masterpiece of world architecture of the Roman Pantheon. The method involves performing the proportional-metrological analysis of the forms using the results of three-dimensional laser scanning. The sequence of actions allowing receiving extremely reliable dimensional drawings of necessary elements of an architectural monument is presented. The analysis suggests that the design metrological module of the Pantheon was a Roman foot of 0.445 m. A detailed analysis of the size of the rotunda plan made it possible to confirm the hypothesis that the design was based on the use of an integer analogue of the number "PI" - fraction 22/7. In addition, an integer right triangle 5: 12: 13 could be used to construct the right angle and to determine the basic proportions of the elements of the facade of the portico. Apparently, in the process of designing the forms of the Pantheon, the method of harmonizing elements on the basis of the similarity method with a change in their scale was used

More...
Truth and freedom as the axiological foundations of practicing science at the Lvov-Warsaw School

Truth and freedom as the axiological foundations of practicing science at the Lvov-Warsaw School

Author(s): Joanna Zegzuła-Nowak / Language(s): English Issue: 28/2019

The contribution is discussed of the Lvov-Warsaw School (LWS) in determining the axiological dimension of science. By promoting philosophical culture and solid axiological foundations, the School members aspired to imbue the spirit of patriotism and a sense of national community in society. They believed that if science is to serve humanity, it should not develop in an infinite and recalcitrant way. Apart from defining substantive and methodological directives, the LWS scholars regarded it important to draw up axiological frameworks of scientific studies to define their proper tasks and protect them against depreciating factors. Science, in their view, should promote and develop values. As they saw it, science based on clearly defined axiological foundations should not only seek to improve man’s living, but also develop his inner life. Hence, the scholar’s mission should adhere to set values, in particular truth and freedom, imbuing scientific work with the status of crucial and at the same time autonomous field of human activity.

More...
Znaczenie językowe normy prawnej w poznańsko-szczecińskiej szkole teorii prawa w świetle pragmatyzmu analitycznego

Znaczenie językowe normy prawnej w poznańsko-szczecińskiej szkole teorii prawa w świetle pragmatyzmu analitycznego

Author(s): Wojciech Rzepiński / Language(s): Polish Issue: 1/2019

The author first reconstructs standpoints adopted by the scholars from the Poznan-Szczecin school of legal theory regarding the linguistic meaning of a legal norm. This reconstruction allows certain dilemmas related to the adoption of analytic philosophy in the theory of law to be visualized. In the next section of the article, attention is paid to the influence of Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz’s philosophy on the understanding of linguistic meaning within the School. The problem of linguistic meaning may be explained by the definition of equivalence, the core of which is a set of directives of a specific language. Finally, the author comments on the theses of Robert B. Brandom’s analytic pragmatism and the application of the latter to legal theory of Maciej Dybowski. Analytic pragmatism extends semantic research through an attempt to understand practice-related conditions.

More...
Schmerzlokalisation und Körperraum

Schmerzlokalisation und Körperraum

Author(s): Mihai Ometiță / Language(s): German Issue: 1/2020

The paper brings a challenge to Cartesian dualism, while introducing some under-explored manuscript remarks from Wittgenstein’s middle period, which are methodologically and thematically akin to some passages from Merleau-Ponty’s early period. Cartesian dualism relegates pain to mental awareness and location to bodily extension, thus rendering common localizations of pain throughout the body as unintelligible ascriptions. Wittgenstein’s and Merleau-Ponty’s attempts at doing justice to common localizations of pain are mutually illuminating. In their light, Cartesian dualism turns out to involve an objectification and a deappropriation of one’s body. Moreover, Wittgenstein’s unveiling a heterogeneous multiplicity of corporeal spaces (e.g. visual-space, tactile-space, feeling-space) rehabilitates the view, reinforced by Merleau-Ponty, that corporeal pain is intimately related to corporeal localization, while corporeal space is not part of the physical space of things.

More...
Result 761-780 of 923
  • Prev
  • 1
  • 2
  • 3
  • ...
  • 38
  • 39
  • 40
  • ...
  • 45
  • 46
  • 47
  • Next

About

CEEOL is a leading provider of academic eJournals, eBooks and Grey Literature documents in Humanities and Social Sciences from and about Central, East and Southeast Europe. In the rapidly changing digital sphere CEEOL is a reliable source of adjusting expertise trusted by scholars, researchers, publishers, and librarians. CEEOL offers various services to subscribing institutions and their patrons to make access to its content as easy as possible. CEEOL supports publishers to reach new audiences and disseminate the scientific achievements to a broad readership worldwide. Un-affiliated scholars have the possibility to access the repository by creating their personal user account.

Contact Us

Central and Eastern European Online Library GmbH
Basaltstrasse 9
60487 Frankfurt am Main
Germany
Amtsgericht Frankfurt am Main HRB 102056
VAT number: DE300273105
Phone: +49 (0)69-20026820
Email: info@ceeol.com

Connect with CEEOL

  • Join our Facebook page
  • Follow us on Twitter
CEEOL Logo Footer
2025 © CEEOL. ALL Rights Reserved. Privacy Policy | Terms & Conditions of use | Accessibility
ver2.0.428
Toggle Accessibility Mode

Login CEEOL

{{forgottenPasswordMessage.Message}}

Enter your Username (Email) below.

Institutional Login